Brent writes:
Hi Glen,
Thanks for further explaining your views. You are correct in pointing out my error at just lumping you in with all radical behaviorists, Gibsonia's, (including 'new'), embodied cognition and so on. Since all these points of view are so foreign to my way of thinking, it's hard to tell you guys apart, let alone remember what it is you think is important. So I very much appreciate your help so I can better understand you. And THIS is the purpose of canonizer, not "argumentum ad populism".
Glen responds:
Hi Brent,
You keep saying this, but then you seem to contradict it elsewhere. What is the purpose of the "survey" part of it? What difference does it make how many people adhere to a particular position? Don't get me wrong, I like the site because it may allow me to get into a good ol' fashioned intellectual donnybrook. But I think the survey portion is largely meaningless. I did, however, in honor of your endeavor, start a camp. I don't think it is in the right place in the hierarchy though. It should probably have been placed under "Consciousness from detection, reaction and association." I don't agree with much of what they say, but I do agree with some of it. Anywayguess how many people have signed on to my position? None, and around here that is all there is likely to be. Even if there were some adherents from the "embodied cognition" people, the fact that I call myself a radical behaviorist would keep them away, even if they basically agreed with everything I might say. The institutionalized misrepresentation, and de facto censorship, of radical behaviorism is enough to make people want to not be associated in any way with the philosophy. Further, the de facto censorship of behaviorism is so successful, that relatively few people have any understanding of radical behaviorism or behavior analysis.
Brent writes:
I desperately want to know, concisely and quantitatively, what everyone that holds a different point of view believes, in all their subtle differences, and so on. This is not possible for me to create a concise representation of what all you guys believe, so I'm pleading with everyone to help us, collaboratively, get a good concise and quantitative representation of what everyone currently believes.
Most people tend to think their view is more in the minority than they think. Religions do this all the time. Thank you for pointing out that my 10 year old perceptions that representationalism was in the minority, was grossly in error. And I would also assert that your view that your beliefs are in the minority, might also be off, at least a bit. Again, that is another purpose of canonizer.com - to come up with rigorous measurements of such, so people can have a better irrefutable idea of reality. And even though the more popular camps obviously have more influence in the system, I am always arguing for, and supporting how important the minority camps are also. Again, we need to know all of them, concisely quantitatively and efficiently (i.e. not repetitively).
Glen responds:
I am quite sure that I have not underestimated the popularity of radical behaviorism. I am not quite sure about how popular "embodied cognition" is (and I have already argued that much in that position is similar to radical behaviorism), but I doubt it is too popular. I'm not sure I understand what you mean by:
"Again, that is another purpose of canonizer.com - to come up with rigorous measurements of such, so people can have a better irrefutable idea of reality." if it is not a reference to some alleged relation between popularity and "truth."
Brent writes:
You mentioned that my "position doesn't predict anything" but I think differently. We are making not yet proven or testable theoretical predictions about what science is about to show us. And the definitive way we will know that such predictions turn out to be true, is when you and everyone else jumps from your soon to be falsified camps, making falsified predictions - to our camp. And of course the opposite could happen, we could turn out to be wrong, where science will force us to jump to your or some other better camp that was making better predictions all along.
Glen responds:
I'm not sure I understand what you are saying here, but I think you are making pretty standard claims about science and falsification etc. Much of what is said about how science works is nonsense, but even if the hypothetico-deductive model of science, as applied to behavioral issues, was not overly simplistic and overly optimistic, it still would not apply to representationism which is not an hypothesis; it is an assumption.
Brent writes:
You described a phototropic robot:
Say you build a robot that shows a phototropic response.
An array of directional photosensitive transducers drive the
mechanism such that the wheels on the side opposite the
light source turn more than those that are ipsilateral. When
the stimulation is equal, the thing goes to the light source.
Any alleged "representation" is utterly gratuitous.
I think ALL this is representation, and not gratuitous at all.
Glen responds:
That's pretty much what I said (and it is a claim to which you did not respond as far as I can tell). For you, it appears, there is no causation that is not a kind of representation. I find that a very, very damaging aspect of your position.
Brent writes:
We start with the initial cause of the perception process, the surface of the strawberry reflecting 700nm light. The first causally downstream 'representation' in the seeing perception process is the reflected 700nm light.
Glen responds:
See? For you everything is representation. SoI ask again, is the motion of the distal end of a lever a representation of the motion of the proximal end? What ISN'T representation in your view?
Brent writes:
This light is a representation of the strawberry, thought it is not fundamentally, and surely not phenomenally, anything like the strawberry. In order to get a representation of the strawberry from the light, you must properly interpret the causal properties of the light.
Glen responds:
But, since everything for you is representation, "interpret[ing] the causal properties of light" must be more representation. Solight hits the retina. The receptors "fire." These cause other neurons to "fire." At some point, however, I'm guessing that you will claim that "interpretation" takes place. No? But this must have to do with nerves that are in some sense "afferent" with respect to the neural representation. There are "nerves that go to the representation." But if the nerves are affected in some systematic way by the representation aren't they simply MORE representation? What makes one set of firings that are systematically related to the thing seen a representation and some other set "interpretation"? After all, we have one seamless series of connections. The light (according to you) is a representation of the object - the light hits the retina and makes another representation and so on. But all there is all the way down is, so to speak, "nerves firing as a result of other nerves firing." That all sounds like more representation (by your usage) to me. Doesn't it to you?
Brent writes:
And every other causally downstream representation has the same ineffable problem - they must be properly interpreted to extract the meaning.
Glen responds:
OKbut of what does this interpretation consist? Does it involve any neurons that "receive information" from the brain area(s) currently composing the "representation" or, I guess, within which the representation is held? What makes these neural firings "interpretation" and not more "representation." I guess you might say that what makes these interpretation and not representation is that activity here causes behavior.
Brent writes:
This is also true for your phototropic robot. The transducers must be set up properly, so some causal properties somewhere in the light detection process, even if it is only the light itself, so that it steers the robot.
Glen responds:
You mangled this sentence a bit Brent (or so it seems to me), but I think that you are saying what I said above, and that the "evidence of interpretation" is the behavior of the robot. The behavior is not the "seeing," I'm sure you will argue, but it suggests that the representation has been "interpreted." No? But this does not answer my question. If all we have is receptors that "fire" in ways systematically related to the light reflected from the object, attached to nerves that "fire" in ways systematically related to the firing of the receptors, and so on, all there is is more copying. Right? Yet suddenly, this copying becomes "interpretation of the copy," in a totally unexplained way. Further, the position seems to imply that behavior is somehow systematically related to the neural activity that immediately preceded it, in a way similar to the way the reflected light is related to the object from which it was reflected, i.e., related in the way we mean when we say it is a "representation") . No? Its all just stuff that happens that is systematically related to the stuff that immediately follows and so on, at any step of which we can say of the systematicity that it is "representation." Isn't that what you meant when you said of the phototropic robot, "I think ALL this is representation, and not gratuitous at all"? And then you proceeded to talk about the causal chain leading from stimulus to response. But, as I said, the end of the chain, must somehow be related to the stimulus in the same way that any of the earlier representations were related to still earlier representations. So behavior is a "representation" of the stimulus? This seems to be nonsense. Plus, as I have been trying to point out, you want to say that it is ALL representation but, somehow, at some point, it is "interpretation." The position is reduced to gibberish by its own inconsistencies.
Brent writes:
All these causal representations, including the ones that must be interpreted appropriately as ones and zeros, can be considered as abstract knowledge. Their causal properties can be used to control yet other properties that cause yet more behavior. The big difference between this and conscious knowledge, is that our knowledge is represented with phenomenal properties of the 'gray matter' that can be unified together into our world of unified awareness. Things included in this unified working space include phenomenal representations of us - or our 'spirit', represented as 'looking' out of our knowledge of our eyes, at the strawberries - even though this unified phenomenal knowledge of our spirit looking at the strawberries, has no referent in reality.
Glen responds:
I'm sorry, but this sounds more and more like obfuscationism and gibberish. Sounds to me like you are saying that there is all this transfer of information from state to state (and that is ALL there is), each state having the relation to the previous state that could be described as "representation," all the way to behavior with respect to "what is seen," and some place magic happens.
Brent writes:
You say: "The "must be" implies some sort of logical machinery behind the declaration, but I see none." and you always only focus on the resulting behavior. And to me, this is evidence that you don't yet fully understand what we are saying.
Glen responds:
Then show precisely where I have demonstrated this misunderstanding. Seems to me that the "evidence" you have that I have misunderstood is that I am ridiculing the position.
Brent writes:
When we use a digital camera that has an array of pixels that can be one (for red) or zero (for green) we can take a picture of the strawberry patch. But these digital ones and zeros must be property interpreted as strawberry color and leaf color, before you can have enough knowledge to allow one to pick the strawberry.
Glen responds:
I understand what you are saying, and I always have. What I am pointing out is that it is internally-inconsistent and devoid of sense. Either "it" is all "representation," as you said earlier, or there is "representation" and "interpretation," as you say immediately above. Which is it?
Brent writes:
Also, instead of digital memory, you could have some phenomenal brain matter or a neural correlate that had a red quale to be used to represent the strawberry, and neural correlate that had a green phenomenal property to represent the leaves. You would still have to appropriately interpret the red, as the strawberry, and the green, as the leaves, in order to pick the strawberry. But the big difference is, these representations are phenomenally like something, and red and green are phenomenally very different from each other. And you don't have to have any behavior wired to this conscious knowledge for these phenomenal facts of the matter (there is much more to the representations than just causal properties) to be true.
Glen responds:
Again, this mostly sounds like gibberish to me, so I guess you could say that I don't understand your position. But I think it sounds like gibberish, not because it is profound and difficult, but because it is devoid of sense. And it is devoid of sense because it embraces the mereological fallacy (i.e., some brain part "interprets"), and it is simply internally inconsistent.
Brent writes:
Have I converted you to our camp yet? ;) If not, I hope you get a camp started so I have a good concise reference that will help me better know just what it is you believe, and so I can know just how many people agree with you or like thinking of things in this way.
Brent Allsop
Glen responds:
As I said, I have already "set-up" a camp, but I expect no adherents. Most academicians are representationlists, as are most amateurs, because the camera metaphor is easily pushed. It is easy to forget that a photograph is a representation because it engenders some of the "effects" of the thing that it is a photograph of. But this sort of representation (the photo) requires eyes, a brain, and ultimately a body for it to be "interpreted." But once you put the copy inside the brain, the metaphorical nature becomes clear. With what eyes do we see this inner representation, and to what brain are these eyes connected? But that is where I began my criticism, so I must be done for now.